12/27/2014

Three Great Wounds


Recently, I've been reading the fascinating book, Paradoxical Life : Meaning, Matter, and the Power of Human Choice by Andreas Wagner. It's definitely a must-read. But the chapter on human choice about perspectives in science reminded me the discussion we had in a humanities class I took in my freshmen year, so I thought it is worth writing about.

Since the day humans have concluded that they are the only living beings with consciousness, we have associated the idea of being human with the idea of being unique, and being at the center of the universe. I guess it's due to the narcissism of being human, we have never considered the possibility that there may be a form of life which deserves to be more unique, and not yet discovered because of the limitations of our observational capabilities. At this point, it's worth to mention the three great breakthroughs in history, which disappointed the human race on their uniqueness very deeply. Each and every of these breakthroughs were accomplished by human choice, a choice about scientific perspective, as Wagner argues in his book. What Wagner says is that the sufficient evidence for a scientific theory may be present  and ready for interpretation for centuries; but it takes courage, courage to choose, to interpret them in a novel way. Humans bred animals and plants, observed the diversities and similarities between species for centuries before Darwin. Physicists measured the speed of light and tried to explain why it stays constants for any frame of reference before Einstein. But those giants took the courage to choose a completely different perspective to look at the present data, considering the possibilities of being wrong, discouraged, or abandoned and humiliated by the scientific societies. 

I guess best way to mention these three great wounds of human history, carved by Copernicus, Darwin and Freud, is to give the floor to Sigmund Freud himself first. It is also worth to mention the impressive paragraph from the book Life's Ratchet : How molecular machines extract order from chaos, by Peter M. Hoffmann.

“Humanity has in the course of time had to endure from the hands of science two great outrages upon its naive self-love. The first was when it realized that our earth was not the center of the universe, but only a tiny speck in a world-system of a magnitude hardly conceivable; this is associated in our minds with the name of Copernicus, although Alexandrian doctrines taught something very similar. The second was when biological research robbed man of his peculiar privilege of having been specially created, and relegated him to a descent from the animal world, implying an ineradicable animal nature in him: this transvaluation has been accomplished in our own time upon the instigation of Charles Darwin, Wallace, and their predecessors, and not without the most violent opposition from their contemporaries. But man's craving for grandiosity is now suffering the third and most bitter blow from present-day psychological research which is endeavoring to prove to the ego of each one of us that he is not even master in his own house, but that he must remain content with the veriest scraps of information about what is going on unconsciously in his own mind. We psycho-analysts were neither the first nor the only ones to propose to mankind that they should look inward; but it appears to be our lot to advocate it most insistently and to support it by empirical evidence which touches every man closely.” 
- Sigmund Freud, Introduction to Psychoanalysis

“In our belief that we are the center of the universe, we have assumed much, just to be proven wrong time and again: No, the solar system does not revolve around Earth. No, the universe does not end beyond Pluto, or even beyond our Milky Way galaxy, but it is much bigger than we ever thought, full of stars in some places, but for the most part filled with staggering emptiness. No, there is no special life force—our bodies are part of nature, run by molecules. And no, we are not a separate creation from all the other animals, but are their close cousins—all, including ourselves, historical accidents of evolution. In short, we are lucky to be here.” 
- Peter M. Hoffman, Life's Ratchet : How molecular machines extract order from chaos


11/04/2014

On Causality

One of the recent issues that I’ve been reading on is the concept of causality, initiated by the motivation that (hopefully) I can have a view about it on my own. The great thing about reading on causality is that, the more you try to construct your own view of it, more you have to digest information coming from different fields, such as philosophy, statistics, cognitive sciences, physics, etc. Additionally, the concept of causality comes with many other concepts like time and universal determinism, which must be investigated deeply by their own. What I am interested in, is to have a mathematical point of view whether there might be a necessary connection between events or not, in terms of the information coming from nature. This question also involves the mathematical definition of the concept of time, whether it exists, and if it does, the direction of its flow. Although there has been, and still is, a huge discussion on causality among philosophers, I find it sufficient to mention the ideas of David Hume and Immanuel Kant, in order to go on with the mathematical perspective of causality. For those who are interested in the history of the philosophical discussions upon this topic, I would suggest them to take a look at [1] for a very brief introduction.

Let us begin with what Hume suggested on causal relations. Assume that you are standing on a cliff, throwing rocks over the side, and a few seconds later, you hear them crash. When you repeat this experiment ninety-nine times, you would expect to hear the sound of crash at the a hundredth time if you throw a rock over the cliff. This is because you would think that throwing a stone causes the sound of crash, due to the past ninety-nine realizations. You had experienced it long enough to assume that there is a causal connection between the event of throwing a rock over the cliff, and the event of hearing the sound of crash. Hume, on the other hand, claims that, the causal connection you’ve just derived between these two events are nothing more but a constant conjuctionThey may seem conjoined, but this does not and cannot imply that these events are connected. This phrase may sound similar to people who are involved with statistics, in which an equivalent phrase is used : “Correlation does not imply causation.”

Hume claims that the If one event always follows another, we have an intention, a habit, to believe the first causes the second; but it is impossible to prove, empirically or logically, that the first event is the cause of the second. It is the force of habit that makes us derive necessary connections from constant conjunctions. More we perceive these constant conjunctions, we develop a stronger expectation about how the chain of events will continue.

"It appears, then, that this idea of a necessary connexion among events arises from a number of similar instances which occur of the constant conjunction of these events; nor can that idea ever be suggested by any one of these instances, surveyed in all possible lights and positions. But there is nothing in a number of instances, different from every single instance, which is supposed to be exactly similar; except only, that after a repetition of similar instances, the mind is carried by habit, upon the appearance of one event, to expect its usual attendant, and to believe that it will exist. This connexion, therefore, which we feel in the mind, this customary transition of the imagination from one object to its usual attendant, is the sentiment or impression from which we form the idea of power or necessary connexion. Nothing farther is in the case [2].” - David Hume.

There is also a long discussion on Immanuel Kant’s view on causality, and his answer to Hume, which can be found in [3]. Kant also agrees with Hume that a causal connection cannot be proved, but he claims that human mind applies the concept of causal connection as a precondition to understand and make sense of the experimental data. Causal connections are not habits driven empirically from constantly conjoined events. We have the concept of causal connection a priori to our experiences. Kant also went one step further, and he identified causality with the rule of natural law, which the rules that scientists discover. He claimed that the causal sequences of events are lawful sequences of events, and through these laws, causally connected experiences become possible.

Interpreting Hume and Kant, we can conclude that there isn’t any concrete methodology to claim that an event causes another, even though they are in a temporal order and conjoined. But the more interesting part (for me, at least) is to prove (or disprove) these ideas based on the physical phenomenas that we observe in nature. Up until now, we haven’t studied neither the mathematical nor the physical interpretation of causality. So I would like to re-examine the concept of causality in terms of thermodynamics, relativity and quantum mechanics; where the concept of arrow of time is also comes into picture.

In order to assume that an event causes the other, we automatically think that causes precede their effects, i.e, they have to be in a temporal order, where the cause comes first and the effect comes later. The argument, “causes precede their effects”, could have been a good starting point, if we were to derive a methodology on how to find causal relationships between events. If you still believe in Newtonian physics, you are allowed to jump to the second step, since according to Newton, there exists an absolute time which is independent of any observer, and progresses at a consistent pace through the universe. But today, thanks to Einstein, we have the special theory of relativity that challenges many of our intuitive beliefs about time. Unlike Newton’s absolute time, for Einstein, temporal order in which two events occur is dependent on the observer’s frame of reference. As a result, there is no universal order in which events can be temporally aligned. So if we cannot align events temporally in a universal manner, we cannot assume causes to precede their effects as a prior condition for a causal relation. This brings up the concept of retrocausality, which I will discuss in detail later.

As a result, we have two important properties that belong to a pair of events, which are not sufficient to claim a causal relationship nor by themselves, neither together. The first one is correlation, which is present in any causal relation, but is not sufficient on its own to claim that if two events are correlated, they are also causally related. The second one is the temporal order of events, which depends on our reference of frame, due to special relativity. If I observe event A, after I observe event B; I might confidently conclude that another subject may observe event B, after he observes event A. This gives me the freedom to align two events in both temporal directions. Which, in return, gives rise to problems in terms of thermodynamics, and time-asymetic events.

"The second law of thermodynamics states that in a natural thermodynamic process, there is an increase in the sum of the entropies of the participating systems."

In other words, if you drop black ink into a glass of water, the drop will diffuse, and the water will become grey. If you ignore special relativity, you would never see the events in a reversed order, due to the second law of thermodynamics. How the second law of thermodynamics is possible in a relativistic universe, i.e., the relativistic understanding of thermodynamic time asymmetry, is still an open question, both philosophically and physically [4].

If Newton, and his absolute view of time was right, second law of thermodynamics could provide us, at least, a thermodynamical arrow of time, which we could use as the basis for a methodology on finding causal relationships. You may be willing to sacrifice special relativity, and assume all the events are temporally aligned in a universal manner, and use the time-assymetry and irreversibility (which claims that the chain of events wouldn’t be realizable if we change the order of events) principles to deduce a causal relationship between two events mathematically. Unfortunately, your victory wouldn’t last long. Even though the special relativity is out of the picture, your results would seem to be valid for a small set of coarse-grained [5] systems, such as the systems we observe in our daily lives, containing large-scaled bodies. When you try to apply your model (which acknowledges the universal arrow of time) to small-scaled systems, phenomenas observed in quantum mechanics causes you trouble.

At this point, in order to avoid any confusion, it’s important to mention that if special relativity is out of the picture, the concept of causality still implies that causes precede their effects in a universal temporal order. On the contrary, phenomenas observed in quantum mechanics (QM) disproves the necessity for causes to precede their events, and leave room for the concept of retrocausality [6], i.e., allows an effect to occur before its cause, without the use of the theory of special relativity. A demonstrative example for a retrocausal toy model would be the polarizer experiment, which we will discuss in great detail.

Let us begin with the description of Bell’s Theorem, which states that “The predictions of QM cannot be reproduced by any locally causal mathematical description”. To prove this mathematically, assume that we have a system with a photon source, and two measurement apparatuses, as sketched in the Figure below.

image


Each measurement apparatus contains a polarizing beam splitter, with a preferred orientation angle denoted by a for the one on the left, and by for the one on the right. The measurement result on the left is denoted by \(A=+1\) if the photon is detected to be polarized along \(a\), and \(A= -1\), if its polarization if found to be perpendicular to \(a\). The result of the measurement on the right is similarly denoted by \(B\).

For a given choice of the orientation angles \(a\) and \(b\), QM provides the probabilities  \(p(A,B|a,b,\psi)\) for the four possible outcomes for \({A, B}\), which are \(\{+1,+1\}, \{+1,-1\}, \{-1,+1\},\) and \(\{-1,-1\}\), where \(\psi\) denotes the wave function [7]. As a result, we observe the expectation of individual outcomes as,

\begin{align} E[A] = E[B] = 0. \end{align}

Now, let us define a correlator in terms if QM descriptions, which is equal to the expectation of  the multiplication of variables \(A\) and \(B\). Observations from QM experiments show that the variables are correlated such that

\begin{align}P_{QM}(a,b) = E[AB] = \cos(2a-2b).\end{align}
To propose a local (meaning that \(A\) is independent of \(b\) and \(B\), and \(B\) is independent of \(a\) and \(A\)) and causal mathematical model, we must define the cause and effect in this experiment. Since the we assume that observation of the variable \(A\) (or \(B\)) occurs after the photons are emitted from the source, (recall that we assume the temporal order of events are  independent of the observer in this experiments) it’s convenient to define causes as the inputs \(a\) and \(b\), and the effects as the outputs, which are \(A\) and \(B\), or rather their probability distributions, \(p(A)\) and \(p(B)\), which are associated with the time of measurement. What Bell did, was to introduce the variable \(\lambda\), which represents the set of all properties of each pair of photons just before the measurement is made on them. So as a result, assumption of causality would be violated if \(\lambda\) (or its probability distribution \(p(\lambda)\) were to depend on the free variables associated with the time of measurement. Thus, a general locally causal description specifies the distributions, \(p(\lambda)\)\(p(A|a,\lambda)\), and \(p(B|b,\lambda)\), which must be nonnegative and normalized. Now, let us check if these distributions are consistent with the measurements obtained from the QM experiment, i.e., consistent with (1) and (2).

Writing (2) in terms of the set of distributions we have just defined yields to
\begin{align}E[AB] = \int d \lambda p(\lambda) \sum_{AB}ABP(A|a,\lambda)P(B|b,\lambda).\end{align}
To go further, Bell assumes the validity of the EPR paradox [8], and deduces that \(A\) (and similarly \(B\)) cannot be stochastic, and must instead be completely determined by a and \(\lambda\). In other words, if \(a=b\) , then \(P(A=B)=1\) must hold. Consequently, we can use a deterministic function \(F\) such that

\begin{align*}A=F(a, \lambda),\end{align*}
\begin{align*}B=F(b,\lambda).\end{align*}
Notice that \(F\) is equal to either \(-1\) or \(+1\), which guarantees that \(F^2= 1\). Now we can re-write the correlator expression, which is
\begin{align}P_{Bell}(a,b) = \int d \lambda p(\lambda) F(a,\lambda)F(b,\lambda).\end{align}
Let us introduce a third orientation, c, and note the form
\begin{align}P_{Bell}(a,b) - P_{Bell}(a,c) = \int d \lambda p(\lambda) F(a,\lambda)[F(b,\lambda)-F(c,\lambda)].\end{align}
Recall that \(F^2=1\), which lets us to write
\begin{align}P_{Bell}(a,b) - P_{Bell}(a,c) = \int d \lambda p(\lambda) F(a,\lambda)[F(b,\lambda)-F^2(b,\lambda)F(c,\lambda)],\end{align}
\begin{align}P_{Bell}(a,b) - P_{Bell}(a,c) = \int d \lambda p(\lambda) F(a,\lambda)F(b,\lambda)[1-F(b,\lambda)F(c,\lambda)].\end{align}
Since \(F\) is equal to either \(-1\) or \(+1\),
\begin{align}|F(\cdot, \lambda)| =1,\end{align}
and
\begin{align}|F(a, \lambda)F(b, \lambda) | =1.\end{align}
As the final step, taking the absolute value of the integrant and substituting (9) to the result yields to
\begin{align}|P_{Bell}(a,b) - P_{Bell}(a,c)| \leq \int d \lambda p(\lambda)[1-F(b,\lambda)F(c,\lambda)], \end{align}
\begin{align}|P_{Bell}(a,b) - P_{Bell}(a,c)| \leq 1 - P_{Bell}(a,c).\end{align}
Equation (11) is also known as Bell’s inequality. If the predictions of this experiment could be reproduced by any local and causal mathematical description, we would expect (11) to be consistent with the QM correlator given in (2). But if you insert (1) and (2) in (11), you will see that the inequality is violated. As a result, this tells us that there is no local and causal mathematical description that satisfies the observational outcomes of this experiment. We must relax our model in order to reproduce the experimental predictions of QM.

Let us introduce the retrocausal toy-model, where we choose \(\lambda\) to be the angle of emission of the photons belonging to each pair, which accepts one of the values \(a\)\(a+\pi/2\)\(b\), and \(b+\pi/2\), with equal probabilities, such that
\begin{align}P(\lambda| a,b) = \frac{1}{4}[ \delta( \lambda - a)+\delta( \lambda - a -\frac{\pi}{2})+\delta( \lambda - b)+\delta( \lambda - b -\frac{\pi}{2})].\end{align}
By limiting the values of \(\lambda\) so that the predictions of the model would be consistent with the experiment, the model assumes that the photons are emitted by the source with polarizations which anticipate the directions of apparatuses to be encountered in the future, which is a explicit violation of causality.

Photons’ interaction with each apparatus follows the standard probability rules governed by the Malus’ Law [9], which leads to
\begin{align*}P(A=+1|a,\lambda) = \cos^2(a-\lambda)\end{align*}
\begin{align*}P(A=-1|a,\lambda) = \sin^2(a-\lambda)\end{align*}
which is similarly valid for the variable B.

What we expect, is this distribution to be consistent with the outcomes of QM, which are (1) and (2). Substituting each possible value of \(\lambda\) separately for calculating \(E[A]\) , \(E[B]\) , and \(E[AB]\) , verifies that the retrocausal model described above is consistent with the QM predictions.
In conclusion, mathematical models which reproduce the quantum correlations of pairs of photons can be either directly non-local, or retrocausal. Since non-locallity clashes with general relativity, we would go with the retrocausal representation. Let us conclude this section about the polarizer experiment with Bell’s own words,

“ The more closely one looks at the fundamental laws of physics, the less one sees of the laws of thermodynamics. The increase of entropy emerges only for large complicated systems, in an approximation depending on ‘largeness’ and ‘complexity.’ Could it be that causal structure emerges only in something like a ‘thermodynamic’ approximation, where the notions ‘measurement’ and ‘external field’ become legitimate approximations? Maybe that is part of the story, but I do not think it can be all. Local commutativity does not for me have a thermodynamic air about it. …” - Bell.


Lets put the pieces together. Special relativity tells us that the temporal order of events are subjective, therefore if we are trying to make a causal relation between two events, using the information about their order in time would be meaningless. Even though we ignore special relativity and go with the absolute view of time, phenomenas observed in quantum mechanics leave room for cases where effects occur before their causes.

If you think it the other way around, it would actually be a great achievement, if we could truly prove that there are cases, in which the effects occur before their causes. Because this would mean, we have proven that an event is the cause of another, even though they are aligned in the opposite direction of thermodynamical arrow of time. (To be honest, if we could only prove that an event is the cause of the other, I wouldn’t mind about their temporal orientation.) At this point, we must be careful, and interpret the meanings of cause and effect in the polarizer experiment in more detail. We took the inputs (the initial conditions, \(\lambda\)) as causes, and outputs (variables \(A\) and \(B\)) as effects. What makes us think that the choice of initial conditions constitutes a cause for the outcomes of \(A\) and \(B\) If the mathematically causal model was consistent with QM observations, would this prove that causal relations could be deduced from this experiment? Recall that the causal description specifies the distributions, \(p(\lambda)\), \(p(A|a,\lambda)\), and \(p(B|b,\lambda)\). If \(p(A|a,\lambda) \neq p(A)\) (or \(p(B|b,\lambda) \neq p(B)\) ), these distributions can only imply that the variable \(A\) (or \(B\)) is dependent on the variables \(\lambda\), and \(a\) (or \(b\)). However, statistical dependence is not sufficient to demonstrate the presence of such a causal relationship. Correlation does not imply causation.

Consequently, we have to find a ground property, which, by its own, can give us a sense of a necessarily causal relation between two events, regardless of their temporal order. Notice that this inference re-defines the conventional concept of causality, by excluding the condition that causes must precede their effects.

At this point, in order to go further, it is useful to make a distinction between necessary and sufficient causes.

In logic, if event A is a necessary cause of event B, then the presence of B necessarily implies the presence of event A. The presence of event A, however, does not imply that event B will occur. On the other hand, If event A is a sufficient cause of event B, then the presence of event A necessarily implies the presence of event B. However, another cause event C may alternatively cause event B. Thus the presence of event B does not imply the presence of event A [10].

Let event A be a necessary cause of event B, and as an observer, assume that I have no information about this causal relationship. If I observe event B, this means that I have to observe event A at some point in my own temporal arrow, to at least predict some association between these two events. So you see the problem here. If there is no restriction on the temporal order (or if we are considering the possibility of retrocausality), I might never observe event A, and never be able to make a causal connection in between. Furthermore, I might observe another event, say event C, which is also associated with event B, and I might mistakenly conclude that event C causes event B, even though there is no causal connection in between.

Up until this point, since we have discussed the mathematical aspect of causality in terms of thermodynamics, relativity, and quantum mechanics; temporal order of events caused us a big trouble. One may reasonably wonder, if we could make causal connections between events in a  way that we can pragmatically infer the outcomes, and apply these inferences to our daily little lives, where we assume causes precede their events as a god given property of causality. As a result, the question boils down to the following: If correlation doesn’t imply causation alone, can correlation plus the temporal order of events give us an idea about causation?

Event though there is a huge research carried out by statisticians on this field, sadly, the answer is still no.

In order to understand why, let us consider the following famous scenario proposed by A. Fischer [11]. Assume that you have the event of smoking, and you have the event of lung cancer, which are strongly correlated. You also have the temporal order of these events, coming from your observed data (which are lung cancer patients), that the action of smoking precedes the disease. Since we assumed that causes precede their events, we may reasonably conclude that smoking causes lung cancer; which is a conclusion that Fischer disagrees.

What if I told you, that there is a hidden factor in between, i.e., a lurking variable, a so called smoking-cancer-gene, which causes both lung cancer and intention to smoke (i.e., nicotine craving)? If that was the case, although we would still observe a strong correlation between smoking and lung cancer, the decision to smoke or not would have no impact on whether you got the disease. This is also called the Simpson’s Paradox [12], which is the case that including a lurking variable causes you to re-think the direction of an association.

To help addressing problems like what I just described above, Judea Pearl [13], introduced a causal calculus [14] (also called do calculus). He argues that the problem with the lurking variable, is that we try to predict the outcomes of an interventional problem, by using the observational data. What it means is the following: If you collect 100 people from the street, half of them being smokers and half of them not, you cannot jump to the conclusion that smoking causes cancer, due to any lurking variable, like our smoking-cancer-gene. To break causal connections between any lurking variables and smoking, you have to intervene, that is to say, collect 100 non-smokers from the street, and force 50 of them to smoke. This is also called a randomized controlled experiment [15], which is, as you might guess, hard to realize in practice. So even though in our absolute time coarse-grained simple world, we are back to the problem of ambiguity in interpreting observational data in terms of causal relations.

Obviously, with mathematical tools available today, it seems hard to deduce a methodology for determining a causal relation. At this point, I think we should stop and think, why do we need to detect the causal relations anyway? As Hume suggested, learning from habit is actually necessary for us to maintain our lives. If I witness people getting lung cancer after they began smoking, having the idea that these two events are only correlated but nothing more, may also convince me to stop smoking and probably save my life. Of course, this may not be the case, and a smoking-cancer-gene may be a valid explanation for the cause of getting lung cancer, but still, I wouldn’t loose anything. So I think, we should give our cognitive intentions to deduce causal relations the credit they deserve. Even though they cannot be proven mathematically, physically, or logically; ability to interpret these correlated events is one of the fundamental functions that helped us survive the natural selection. So instead of trying to derive sharp and exact mathematical descriptions for causal relations, maybe we should relax the conditions a little bit, and try to find with how much reliability we can deduce that an event causes the other. Before jumping to distinct conclusions, we still have a lot to do with what association and correlation provides to us.

References
[2] David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Of the Idea of necessary Connexion, Part ||.

10/15/2014

Feynman on God


I guess this is one of the most impressive interviews of Richard Feynman, who is, without doubt, one of the greatest physicists of the 20th century. He argues that science is not meant to give answers to the metaphysical problems of human existence, but on the contrary, it's constructed on the inferences about nature itself, and how it works in an uncertain but a beautiful way. He talks in such an intimate, excited, and motivating, so to say, in a Feynmanian mood; which makes me smile while watching the joy of defending his ideas. To understand and think on each and every word of this defence in detail, I tried to transcript the video as much as I could. I hope you enjoy it as much as I did.

Richard Feynman on God

If you expected science to give all the answers to the wonderful questions about what we are, where are we going, what is the meaning of the universe is and so on, then I think you could easily become disillusioned and look for some mystic answers to these problems. How a scientist can take a mystic answer, I don’t know because the whole spirit is to understand - well never mind that - I don’t understand that but anyhow - if you think of - the way I think of what we are doing is we’re exploring we’re trying to find as much as we can about the world. People say to me ‘Are you looking for the ultimate laws of Physics?’. No, I’m not. I’m just looking to find out more about the world, and if it turns outs there was a simple ultimate law that explains everything, so be it! That would be very nice discovery. If it turns out that it’s like an onion with millions of layers and we just get tired of looking at the layers then that’s the way it is! But whatever way it comes out, nature is there and she is gonna come out the way she is. Therefore, when we go on investigating we shouldn’t pre-decide what it is we’re trying to do, except to find out more about it. If you said - but the problem is why do you find out more about? If you thought that you were trying to find out more about it because you’re gonna get an answer to some deep philosophical question, you may be wrong and it may be that you can’t get an answer to that particular question by finding out more about the character of nature. My interest in science is to simply find out the world, and more I find out; better it is. I like to find out.

There are very remarkable mysteries about the fact that they were able to do so many more things that apparently animals can’t do, and other questions like that. But those are the mysteries I want to investigate without knowing the answer to them. So all together I can’t believe the special stories that have been made up about our relationship to the universe because they seem to be too simple, too connected, too local, too prudential! The earth, you came to the earth! One of the aspects of God came to the earth! And look what’s out there! It isn’t in proportion. Anyway it’s no use to argue so I can’t argue it. I’m just trying to tell you why the scientific views that I have do have some effect on my belief. Also another thing, has to do with the question of ‘how do you find out something is true?’. And if you have all these theories of the different religious of all different theories about the thing, then you begin to wonder. Once you start doubting, just like you supposed to doubt. You asked me if the science is true. You said ‘no no you don’t know whats true, you try to find out; and everything is possibly wrong.’ Start understanding religion by saying everything is possibly wrong. Let us see. As soon as you do that you start sliding down of an edge, which is hard to recover from. And so one - with the scientific view - or my fathers view, that we should look to see what’s true and what’s may be, may not be true - Once you start doubting which I think to me is a very fundamental part of my soul is to doubt and to ask. When you doubt and ask, it gets a little harder to believe. 

You see, one thing is I can live with doubt, and uncertainty and not knowing. I think it’s much more interesting to live not knowing then to have answers which might be wrong. I have approximate answers and possible beliefs and different degrees of certainty about different things, but I’m not absolutely sure of anything; and the many things I don’t know anything about! Such as whether it means anything to ask why we’re here, and what the question might mean. I might think about a little bit and if I can’t figure it out then I go to something else. But I don’t have to know an answer. I don’t feel frightened by not knowing things. By being lost in the mysterious universe without having any purpose, which is the way it really is; as far as I can tell, possibly. It doesn’t frighten me.  

9/10/2014

Simulating Life

I would like to introduce Thomas S. Ray, an ecologist who created and developed the Tierra project, a computer simulation of artificial life.


Project Tierra is based on the idea of replication, which is the rule of thumb for being alive. These living beings code their protein sequences in binary, like a bacteria codes them using twenty different types of amino acids (you can think of it as a base-20 coding system).  These beings fight for resources such as processing power and memory, just like the animals fighting for food and shelter. They are attacked by parasites, exposed to random mutations, leave offsprings, evolve, and die. At the end of the day, natural selection decides which beings will live on, i.e., keep their addresses in the memory, and which ones will die out, i.e., simply will be deleted.


In order to internalize how something works, you need to code it. Coding gives you the opportunity to understand how things will turn out in practise. But more importantly, if things doesn’t work out as expected, it helps you to see why. This is the main motivation for Ray and his research team : “We cannot fully define and understand what life is, but we won’t be able to understand it further if we don’t try to simulate it either.”

At this point, we have to mention the pioneer on this subject, Christopher Langton, who is an American computer scientist and one of the founders of the field of artificial life. he developed several key concepts and quantitative measures for cellular automata[1] (CA) and suggested that critical points separating order from disorder could play a very important role in shaping complex systems, particularly in biology [2]. He is also the founder of the problem Langton’s ant [3], which is an informative example to interpret the concept of CA and what Langton suggests. Imagine a plane divided into identical squares, which will be called cells, and each cell has finite number of states. States of these cells are updated according to a static rule. In the problem of Langton’s ant, each cell has two states : they can either be black or white. The ant starts from a random cell, looking at a random direction, and all cells are considered to be white at time zero. If the ant is at a white cell, it turns 90º right,  flips the color of the cell, and moves forward to the next cell. If the ant is at a black cell, it turns 90º left,  again flips the color of the cell, and moves forward to the next cell. These are the two and only rules for this CA. You can see the behaviour of this ant in the animation below. Even the ant seems to be governed by very simple set of rules, the outcomes of this behaviour is fascinating. 



After around 10,000 steps, the ant starts to build a recurrent highway pattern that repeats indefinitely as seen in the figure below (This phenomena is also known as Cohen-Kung theorem[4]). 



The ant converges to this repetitive highway independent of the initial cell and direction, which were chosen randomly. This emergent behaviour - which cannot be proven to converge to a highway eventually - is the best proof for Langtons argument : critical points separating order from disorder could play a very important role in shaping complex systems.

For those who are interested in generating this image by themselves, I’ve attached the MATLAB code for a quick simulation of this CA at the end of this post. 

You can also check the software Avida, a product of project Tierra, which serves like a petri dish that you can watch your binary bacteria grow, replicate, mutate, and evolve.

There are tons of things to read, discuss, and write about life, natural selection, and evolution. But even though we have a long way to go, trying to code life, I guess, is the perfect starting point.


% SIMULATION FOR LANGTON'S ANT %

clear all;clc;
S     = 200;
plane = ones(S);
head  = 1;
% DIRECTION OF THE ANT
% 1 = up
% 2 = down
% 3 = right
% 4 = left
mag       = 200;     %image magnification scale
it        = 0;       %number of iterations
ant       = [randsample(30:50,1) randsample(50:70,1)]; %assign randomly
initialPt = ant;
while it<1e6
    old_ant = ant;
    if plane(ant(1),ant(2))==1 % turn left
        if head==1
            ant(2)=ant(2)-1;
            head  =4;
        elseif head==2
            ant(2)=ant(2)+1;
            head  =3;
        elseif head==3
            ant(1)=ant(1)-1;
            head  =1;
        else
            ant(1)=ant(1)+1;
            head  =2;
        end
    elseif plane(ant(1),ant(2))==0 %turn right
        if head==1
            ant(2)=ant(2)+1;
            head  =3;
        elseif head==2
            ant(2)=ant(2)-1;
            head  =4;
        elseif head==3
            ant(1)=ant(1)+1;
            head  =2;
        else
            ant(1)=ant(1)-1;
            head  =1;
        end
    end
    plane(old_ant(1),old_ant(2)) = 1-plane(old_ant(1),old_ant(2));
    it = it+1;
    if ant(2)>S || ant(2)==0
        imshow(plane,'InitialMagnification',mag)
        break;
    elseif ant(1)>S || ant(1)==0
        imshow(plane,'InitialMagnification',mag)
        break;
    end
end
hold on;
plot(initialPt(1),initialPt(2),'r*')
plot(old_ant(2),old_ant(1),'b*')
legend('Initial Position','Final Position')

8/13/2014

The Neuroscience of Consciousness


A great lecture given by Susan Greenfield, who is a researcher focused on brain physiology, particularly on the brain mechanisms of Parkinson's and Alzheimer's diseases.

What she argues in this lecture is an inspiring idea on modelling any scientific concept on a continuous scale rather than being discrete. When we mention consciousness, we automatically think of it as it exists or not, analogous to thinking of a light bulb being only on or off, or a bit being equal to 1 or 0. What about thinking of a degree of consciousness, modeling it as a variable which can take values between 0 and 1, rather than being only 0 or 1? This perspective also provides answers to the questions about when a foetus becomes 
consciouses, or how much consciouses are you under the influence of drugs or alcohol? I hope you enjoy listening the neuroscientific point of view of such a concept discussed among philosophers and biologist for centuries, and yet cannot be defined nor explained completely.

8/06/2014

Now I am Become Death, the Destroyer of Worlds



For the memory of August 6 and 9, 1945.

One of the greatest minds in the history, and he can’t even look at the camera in the eye.

I guess that’s what makes me watch this over and over again.

Remainder for the ones who does’t know the whole story : Oppenheimer wanted to demonstrate the atom bomb, never encouraged to blow it up over people. But I guess when army spends gigantic amounts of money to something, independent of what it is, they use it.  
"We knew the world would not be the same. A few people laughed, a few people cried. Most people were silent. I remembered the line from the Hindu scripture, the Bhagavad Gita; Vishnu is trying to persuade the Prince that he should do his duty and, to impress him, takes on his multi-armed form and says, 'Now I am become Death, the destroyer of worlds.' I suppose we all thought that, one way or another.
                                                                     - J. Robert Oppenheimer

6/05/2014

Dirayet

Üç saatlik filmleri izlemeye üşendiğimiz, kalın kitaplara başlamaya korktuğumuz, bozulan bir aleti tamir etmeye çalışmak yerine attığımız; kısacası sabırsız ve hevessiz yaşadığımız bu günlerde; yalnızca sabırlı ve tutkulu insanlar tarafından başarılabilecek bir kaç bilimsel dönüm noktasından bahsetmekte fayda olduğunu düşünüyorum. Elbette benim bahsedeceklerim dışında binlerce hikaye var, diğer bilim insanlarına saygısızlık etmek haddime değil. 

Hikayelerden ilki, 16.yy astronomlarından Tycho Brahe’nin gezegenlerin konumu hakkında yaptığı gözlemleri konu alıyor. Kopernik dünyanın evrenin merkezinde olmadığını ve diğer yıldızlarla birlikte güneşin etrafında döndüğünü keşfettikten sonra; sorulan ikinci soru bu döngünün nasıl gerçekleştiği oldu. Brahe’nin bu sorunun çözümü icin önerdiği yöntem şuydu: Eğer gezegenler çok dikkatli gözlenip gökyüzündeki yerleri tam olarak kaydedilirse, gezgenler hakkındaki teoriler açıklığa kavuşabilirdi [1]. Bu yöntem, doğanın anlaşılması yolundaki bilimsel metodun ilk tohumudur : Gerçekliğine inandığınız bir olgu hakkında bilgi toplamak, ve cevabın bu bilginin içinde olduğunu ummak. Bugünkü deyimimizle data’nin model’e uygunluğunu test etmek. Bir an için bu işin gerektirdiği sabrı ve sürekliliği düşünmekte fayda var. Bir sene boyunca her gece yıldızları özenle gözlemleyip konumlarını kaydettiğinizi düşünün. Kaydetmekten kastım koordinat ölçümlerini hassas bir biçimde yapabilen teknolojik aletlerin sizin için oluşturdukları detaylı dosyalar değil. Quadrant ve sextant'lar[2] kullanarak; gecelerce, gözünüzü kırpmadan, üst üste bu ölçümleri hassas bir şekilde yapmaya çalışmak. Kuvvetle muhtemel miyop olmak, uykusuz kalmak, heyecandan açlığını unutmak da bu işe dahil. İşin güzelliği, yalnızca tahta ve pirinçten yapılma ölçüm aletleri sayesinde elde edilmiş gözlemleri kullanarak, o zamanlar Tycho’nun çırağı olan Kepler’in gezegenlerin yörüngelerinin daire değil de elips oldugunu keşfetmesinde yatıyor. Feynman’ın konu hakkındaki yorumu, durumu özetlemeye yetiyor aslında : "İşte ancak bu tür yorucu ve yoğun çalışmalar yoluyla bir şeyler bulunabilirdi." 

İkinci hikayenin kahramanı hepimizin evrim babası olan Charles Darwin, ve 22 yaşında başladığı, beş sene süren Beagle seferi [3]. Beş sene boyunca, deniz tutması, açlık ve kusmalara rağmen, Pasifik’in ortasında planktonların güzelliğini insanların neden takdir etmediğini düşünen, 22 yaşında bir erkekten; daha doğrusu 22 yaşında bir çocuktan bahsediyoruz. Bu seferi bitirdiğinde Darwin 27 yaşındaydı, ve yaptığı yorum şu olmuştu: "As far as I can judge of myself I worked to the utmost during the voyage from the mere pleasure of investigation, and from my strong desire to add a few facts to the great mass of facts in natural science.” . Evrim fikri ilk defa Darwin’den çıkmadı, her şeyi öngördükleri gibi antik Yunanlılar bunu da öngörmüştü elbette. Eminim ki adi tarihe geçmeyen bir çok biyolog da bu fikre katıldı, doğruluğuna inandı; ama kanıtlamak icin kayda değer hiç bir şey yapmadı. Muhtemelen üşendiği icin sıcak evindeki yumuşak koltuğunda çayını içerek evrimi onayladığını ve mantıklı bir fikir oldugunu adı tarihe geçmeyen diğer üşengeç biyologlara anlattı. Onlar da entelektüel bir konuşmanın içinde yer almanın verdiği tatminle bu fikri onayladılar. Ama hiç biri harekete geçip de bunu kanıtlamak icin gereken sabrı ve tutkuyu gösterip veri toplamadı. Bunu gerçekleştiren, kuru kuruya inanmakla tatmin olmayan, ve kanıt aramak icin üşenmeyen Darwin oldu. Adı tarihe geçmeyen biyologlar belki de Darwin’in en güzel yıllarını bir gemide harcadığını düşündü. Adım kadar eminim ki Darwin için o yıllarını Planktonların renklerini inceleyerek geçirmek, mutluluktu.

Son örnek, bana kalırsa yaşadığı talihsizliklere rağmen yılmayarak en büyük sabır örneğini gösteren bilim adamlarından biri : Fransız astronom Guillaume Le Gentil. Gentil, 1761’de Venüs’ün geçişini Pondicherry’den (Hindistan) gözlemleyebilmek için Hint Okyanusu’nda, Mauritius adlı bir adada, Pondicherry’e gidebileceği güvenli bir gemi bulmak için aylarca bekledi. Sefer sırasında, o donemde Fransızlar ile savaşta olan İngilizler Pondicherry’i ele geçirdiği için Mauritius'a geri dönmek zorunda kaldı. Venüs’ün geçişi Gentil denizin ortasında İngilizlerden kaçmaya çalışırken gerçekleştiği için verimli bir gözlem yapamadı, istediği ölçümleri elde edemedi. "Zut alors!"

Kısaca bahsetmekte fayda var. Venüs’ün geçişi (transit of Venus [4]) ender bir olaydır, ve sekiz senede bir gerçekleşir. Peki bu kadar yolu gelip Mauritius’a vardıktan sonra; gözlem şansını kaçırmış olan Gentil neye karar verdi? Sekiz sene daha beklemeye! (Bankamatik sırasında önünüzde duran insan para çekmeye çalışırken kaç dakika beklemeye tahammül edebiliyorsunuz?)

Sekiz sene sonra, 1769’da, Pondicherry tekrar Fransızların eline geçmişti. Gözlemin başarısız olması için ortada görünür bir sebep yoktu; fakat gözlemin gerçekleşeceği gece, hava bulutlu olduğu için, Gentil yine başarısız olmuştu. Doğa bazen hiç beklemediğiniz bir anda sizinle çok güzel dalga geçebilme yeteneğine sahip.

Uzun ve sıkıntılı bir deniz yolculuğunun sonunda, Gentil anavatanına geri dönmeyi başardı; fakat Paris’i terk edeli on sene olmuştu. Kendisinden haber alınamadığı icin ölü ilan edilmiş, karisi ise bu süreçte yeniden evlenmişti. Venüs aşkına!

Son hikaye diğerlerine göre daha hüzünlü bir sonla bitse de, aslında hepsinin anlattığı tek bir ortak nokta var. Şu an içinde bulunduğumuz çağ bize o kadar fazla hassas ölçüm olanağı, o kadar gelişmiş araç gereçler sunuyor ki; bir tanesi bile eksik olduğunda bir deneye sırtımızı kolayca dönebiliyoruz. Sonuca ulaşmak icin sayfalarca işlem yapmamız gerektiğini sezdiğimizde üşenip vazgeçebiliyoruz. Tek bir problem üzerinde bir seneden fazla çalıştığımızda kendimizde sıkılma hakkını görüyoruz; hatta bu durum çevremizdekiler tarafından onaylanarak geçerli hale getiriliyor. Fakat unutmamak lazım ki, insanoğlu olarak buralara kolay gelmedik. Matematik yetersiz kaldığında Calculus’u bulduk, gözlerimiz yetersiz kaldığında teleskobu icat ettik. Yıldızların görmek icin fazla uzakta olduğunu, ışığın yakalamak icin fazla hızlı olduğunu, ya da atomun tartmak icin fazla hafif olduğunu düşünüp de üşenmedik. Önemli olan sonuca ulaşmaktan çok, surecin içinde kaybolmaktan zevk almaktı. Bana kalırsa zaten başka türlüsü olmazdı, olamazdı. 

Kısacası bilim; bilinen metotlar tükendiğinde, alışılageldik ölçüm aletleri yetersiz kaldığında, elde yeterli veri olmadığında, ve inancınız olduğunda başlıyor.

[1] Feynman, 1964’de Cornell Üniversitesinde verdiği Messenger konuşmalarından ( http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Messenger_Lectures ) birincisinin ( Law of Gravitation ) girişinde bu örneği verir. Feynman’ın tum Messenger konuşmalarını izlemek için : http://research.microsoft.com/apps/tools/tuva/#data=3%7C%7C%7C
[2] Tycho’nun gözlemleri için ürettiği astronomik araçlar : http://www.tychobrahe.com/UK/mechanica.html


5/14/2014

Bilim, deli gömlegindeki hayal gücüdür

Bugün bir sonuca vardım: yaşadığımız uzayda edindiğimiz fiziksel deneyimler insana çok şey kaybettiriyor. Tecrübelerimizle birlikte doğaya dair bir model geliştiriyoruz; akla yatkın(!), mantıklı bir model. Küçükken duvara attığınız bir top sekerek size geri geliyor, bunu belki de yüzlerce kez tecrübe ediyorsunuz.  Sonuç olarak mantıklı olan topun duvara çarptığında öbür tarafa geçemeyeceği oluyor. Makro boyuttaki bir hayat için, tüme varmakta sıkıntı çıkarmayacak bir tecrübe. Ayni şekilde, siz bu bilgisayar ekranına baktığınız - bilgisayar ekranını gözlemlediğiniz - için, ekranda meydana gelen bir değişiklik yok. Akla yatkın, değil mi? Çünkü geçmişte tecrübe ettiğinizden farklı bir şey yaşamadınız, modelden dışarı çıkan bir durum değildi bu. Çoğu zaman isinizi kolaylaştıracak olsa da, ayni anda iki farklı yerde de bulunamadınız mesela. Olsa fena olmazdı aslında; ama mantıksız. Kısacası bir olayın olabilirliği, sizin fiziksel olarak deneyimlediklerinizin ne kadar içinde olduğu ile alakalı. Evrimsel anlamda, hayatinizi devam ettirebilmeniz için güzel bir mekanizma; fakat hayal gücüne at gözlüğü takan bir durum. Özellikle de is makro boyuttan bir nötron büyüklüğüne inip, kuantum mekaniğine geldiği zaman.


Feynman’ın çok içten bir sözü var bu konu hakkında : "I think I can safely say that nobody understands quantum mechanics.” Çok doğru! Doğru, çünkü insan beyni bunu anlamak icin evrilmedi. Doğru, çünkü hiç aynı anda iki farklı yerde olmadık, kutuyu açtığımızda kedinin hayatta oldugunu zaten biliyorduk, ve herkes gözünü bize dikmesine rağmen parçacıklardan oluşmaya devam ettik. Eğer fiziksel tecrübelerinizin size getirdiği sınırlamaları kaldırmayı kabul eder, okuduğunuz şeylere anında “ama bu olamaz ki”  tepkisini vermezseniz, insanoğlu olarak yeni yeni keşfetmeye başladığımız, izlediğiniz tüm bilimkurgu filmlerinden daha eğlenceli, ve gerçek olan bir dünyayı deneyimlemeniz mümkün. Çünkü doğa, gerçekten de bir tanecik seviyesine indiğinde çok büyüleyici davranıyor. 


Belki duymuşsunuzdur, bundan iki sene önce ilk kuantum işlemci %49 güvenilirlik ile 15’i asal çarpanları olan 3 ve 5’e ayırmayı başardı [1]. Geçenlerde kuantum mekaniği üzerine izlediğim TED seminerlerinden birinde konuşmacı, dinleyicilerin yüzünü gülümseten su cümleyi kurdu,
“So your homework for tonight is to figure out how to factorize 15 into 3 and 5 by using only 5 atoms!” 
İnsan bu noktadan sonra, isin fiziğini yalnızca kıyısından köşesinden de olsa anlamaya yaklaşmak umuduyla, internette olan tüm içeriği taramaya başlıyor. En basit haliyle, kuantum bilgisayarların çalışma mantığı şöyle özetlenebilir:


Bilgiyi manipüle edebilmeniz icin - yani bir bilgisayar yapabilmeniz icin - öncelikle bilgiyi maddenin fiziksel bir özelliğine yükleyebilmeniz gerek. Nöronlarınız bunu difüze ettikleri sodyum, potasyum, kalsiyum ve klorid iyonlarının yükleri ile toplama / çıkarma işlemleri gerçekleştirerek yapıyor. DNA’nız, ihtiyacınız olan proteinin bilgisini m-RNA’daki 4 çeşit nükleik asidin dizilimine kodlayarak bu isi gerçekleştiriyor - bir nevi quaternary sayı sistemini kullanıyor. Bu yazıyı okumak icin kullandığınız klasik bilgisayarınız, bilgiyi ikili (binary) sayı sistemine çevirip, 1 ve 0’lari hafızasında bulundurduğu çok küçük manyetik halkaları (toroid) saat yönünde ya da saat yönünün tersinde polarize ederek tutuyor. Bu halkalar bir bitlik bilgiyi temsil ediyor, yani kaç halkanız varsa o kadar bitiniz oluyor. Kuantum bilgisayarların klasik bilgisayardan farkı ise, manyetik halkalar yerine elektronlar kullanması, ve ikili bilgiyi elektronların kendi ekseni etrafında saat yönüne (up-spin) ya da saat yönünün tersine (down-spin) dönmesi olarak kodlaması. Haliyle sezgisel olarak varacağınız sonuç, kaç elektronunuz varsa o kadar bitiniz olacağı, fakat isler tam da bu noktada güzelleşiyor; cünkü bir elektron, es zamanlı olarak, hem saat yönünde, hem de tersine dönebiliyor. Peki bu ne demek? 


Tek başına bir quantum bit - yani bir qubit - ayni anda hem 1 hem 0  olabildiği icin 2 bitlik bilgi taşıyabiliyor. 2 qubit, es zamanlı olarak, {00,01,10,11} olabiliyor: 4 bitlik bilgi. Genellersek N qubit, 2^N bitlik bilgi tutabiliyor. Bu, yalnızca 9 elektron ile 1 gigabit bilgi demek! Bu, evrim gibi parametre sayısı düşünebildiğimizin ötesinde olan sistemlerin modellenebilmesi demek. Bu, yaklaşık 14 milyar yıl sürecek bir işlemin dakikalar mertebesinde yapılabilecek olması demek. Çok iyi değil mi ama?


Su an kucağınızda bir kuantum bilgisayar olmamasının bir çok sebebi var elbette. Bir elektronun kuantum mekaniği ilkelerine göre davranması icin çevresinden tam anlamıyla izole edilmesi gerekiyor, ki bu bugünün teknolojisi ile gerçekleştirilmesi emek isteyen bir durum. Çevresi ile etkilesen elektron, quantum decoherence [2] nedeniyle rastgelelik özelliğini yitiriyor, ve ayni anda tek durumda bulunarak taşıdığı bilgiyi bir bite indiriyor. Bir nevi baktığınız zaman utanıyor.


Algılarımıza ters düşen olgulardan biri de zamanın simetrisi, yani fiziksel bir olayın zamanda geri döndürülebilmesi. Bunun nedensellik ilkesi sebebiyle doğru olamayacağı hepimize mantıklı geliyor; çünkü termodinamiğin ikinci yasası ile yönetilen bir evrende yaşıyoruz: entropi sürekli artıyor. 


Bir bardak suya bir damla lacivert mürekkep damlattığınızı, ve bu süreci kameraya çektiğinizi düşünün. Mürekkep suyun içinde difüze olacak, ve bir süre sonra bardaktaki su açık mavi bir renk alacak. Deneyimlediğimiz tüm diğer olaylarda olduğu gibi, entropi artacak. Simdi filmi geri sarin, dağılan mürekkep tekrar bir damla haline geri geliyor. Saçma, çünkü bu, entropinin azaldığı, yani günlük hayatta deneyimleyemeyeceğiniz bir sistem. Haliyle akla yatkın değil, mantığa tersolmaz öyle şey, vesaire, vesaire…


Simdi bu filme biraz zoom yapıp, teker teker moleküllerin etkileşimine baktığımızı düşünün: birbiriyle çarpışan su ve lacivert boyaya. Burada geri döndürülemeyecek bir fiziksel durum yok. Brown hareketindeki [3] rastgelelikten ötürü, bu iki molekül, tekrar çarpışıp eski konumlarına da dönebilirdi; fakat büyük resme baktığınızda mürekkep hiçbir zaman bir damla olduğu duruma geri dönmüyor. Huw Price’in [4] makro - mikro anlamda nedensellik üzerine söylediklerine burada yer vermekte fayda var.
"One problem with this approach is that the distinction between cause and effect requires coarse-graining (çok parçacıklı). On a fine-grained view, where one keeps track of the motion of all relevant molecules, there simply is no change in entropy. Thus on a fine-grained view, one must say that the distinction between cause and effect vanishes, leaving us without an unambiguous distinction between cause and effect.” [5]
Tüm bu okuduklarım - en azından benim icin - okuyabileceğim herhangi bir bilim kurgu romanından çok daha heyecanlı, keşfetmesi müthiş haz veren konular. Eğer mantığınızın üzerindeki tüm kısıtlamaları kaldırıp, hayal gücünüzü rahat bırakırsanız; emin olun mükemmel zevk alıyorsunuz. Sonuçta zamanda geri gitmekten, ayni anda iki farklı yerde olmaktan, hızlı giden nesnelerin kısalmasından, duvara attığınızda öbür tarafa gecen elektronlardan bahsediyoruz! Ve bunlar, sizi oluşturan atomlar kadar gerçek!